Апстракција — разлика између измена

С Википедије, слободне енциклопедије
Садржај обрисан Садржај додат
.
Ред 1: Ред 1:
{{Short description|Процес генерализације}}
{{друго значење3|Апстракција (објектно-оријентисано програмирање)}}
{{друго значење3|Апстракција (објектно-оријентисано програмирање)}}
'''Апстракција''' (лат. ''abstractio'') је мисаоно издвајање неких [[особина]] и својстава [[предмет]]а од самог предмета, као и апстрактан појам издвојен од нечега [[конкретан|конкретног]] за који је везан. ''Апстрахирати'' или ''апстраховати'' (нем. ''abstrahieren''): вршити апстракцију, и не узети (узимати) нешто у обзир, не обазрети се, не обазирати се на нешто. ''Апстрактно'': добијено апстракцијом, мисаоно; супротно од [[конкретно]].
'''Апстракција''' (лат. ''abstractio'') је:
Фактички, када је нешто апстрактно, то значи да се нешто не односи само на једну појединост, већ на неку већу целину, скуп нечега и сл. ''Апстрактно мишљење'' је врста [[мисао|мишљења]] која се одликује тиме да високо надилази перцептивни ниво и конкретне појаве и да оперише апстрактним симболима.<ref>Овај део чланка је преузет из књиге Ивана Видановића „[[Речник социјалног рада]]“ уз одобрење аутора.</ref>
# мисаоно издвајање неких [[особина]] и својстава [[предмет]]а од самог предмета;
# апстрактан појам издвојен од нечега [[конкретан|конкретног]] за који је везан.


== Порекло ==
'''Апстрахирати''' или '''апстраховати''' (нем. ''abstrahieren''):
{{рут}}
# вршити апстракцију;
Thinking in abstractions is considered by [[anthropologist]]s, [[archaeologist]]s, and [[sociologist]]s to be one of the key traits in [[modern human behaviour]], which is believed to have developed between 50,000 and 100,000 years ago. Its development is likely to have been closely connected with the development of human [[language]], which (whether spoken or written) appears to both involve and facilitate abstract thinking.
# не узети (узимати) нешто у обзир, не обазрети се, не обазирати се на нешто.


=== Историја ===
'''Апстрактно''': добијено апстракцијом, мисаоно; супротно од [[конкретно]].
''Abstraction'' involves [[Inductive reasoning|induction]] of ideas or the synthesis of particular facts into one general theory about something. It is the opposite of ''specification'', which is the analysis or breaking-down of a general idea or abstraction into concrete facts. Abstraction can be illustrated by [[Francis Bacon]]'s ''[[Novum Organum]]'' (1620), a book of modern scientific philosophy written in the late [[Jacobean era]]<ref name="Hesse">Hesse, M. B. (1964), "Francis Bacon's Philosophy of Science", in A Critical History of Western Philosophy, ed. D. J. O'Connor, New York, pp. 141–52.</ref> of England to encourage modern thinkers to collect specific facts before making any generalizations.
Фактички, када је нешто апстрактно, то значи да се нешто не односи само на једну појединост, већ на неку већу целину, скуп нечега и сл.


Bacon used and promoted [[inductive reasoning|induction]] as an abstraction tool; it complemented but was distinct from the ancient [[deductive]]-thinking approach that had dominated the intellectual world since the times of Greek philosophers like [[Thales]], [[Anaximander]], and [[Aristotle]].<ref>{{Citation|last=Klein|first=Jürgen|title=Francis Bacon|date=2016|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/francis-bacon/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2016|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2019-10-22}}</ref> Thales (c. 624–546 BCE) believed that everything in the universe comes from one main substance, water. He deduced or specified from a general idea, "everything is water," to the specific forms of water such as ice, snow, fog, and rivers.
'''Апстрактно мишљење''' је врста [[мисао|мишљења]] која се одликује тиме да високо надилази перцептивни ниво и конкретне појаве и да оперише апстрактним симболима.<ref>Овај део чланка је преузет из књиге Ивана Видановића „[[Речник социјалног рада]]“ уз одобрење аутора.</ref>

Modern scientists can also use the opposite approach of abstraction, or going from particular facts collected into one general idea, such as the motion of the planets ([[Isaac Newton|Newton]] (1642–1727)). When determining that the sun is the center of our solar system ([[Copernicus]] (1473–1543)), scientists had to use thousands of measurements to finally conclude that Mars moves in an elliptical orbit about the sun ([[Kepler]] (1571–1630)), or to assemble multiple specific facts into the law of falling bodies ([[Galileo]] (1564–1642)).

== Теме ==

===Compression===

An abstraction can be seen as a [[data compression|compression]] process,<ref>{{Citation |first=Gregory |last=Chaitin |author-link=Gregory Chaitin | url=http://www.umcs.maine.edu/~chaitin/sciamer3.pdf | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150509165230/http://www.umcs.maine.edu/~chaitin/sciamer3.pdf | archive-date=2015-05-09 |title=The Limits Of Reason |journal=Scientific American |volume=294 |issue=3 |pages=74–81 |year=2006|pmid=16502614 |doi=10.1038/scientificamerican0306-74 |bibcode=2006SciAm.294c..74C }}</ref> mapping multiple different pieces of [[wikt:constituent|constituent]] data to a single piece of abstract data;<ref>[[Murray Gell-Mann]] (1995) "[http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/cplx.6130010105/pdf What is complexity? Remarks on simplicity and complexity by the Nobel Prize-winning author of The Quark and the Jaguar]" ''Complexity'' states the 'algorithmic information complexity' (AIC) of some string of bits is the shortest length computer program which can print out that string of bits.</ref> based on similarities in the constituent data, for example, many different physical cats map to the abstraction "CAT". This conceptual scheme emphasizes the inherent equality of both constituent and abstract data, thus avoiding problems arising from the distinction between "abstract" and "[[concrete (philosophy)|concrete]]". In this sense the process of abstraction entails the identification of similarities between objects, and the process of associating these objects with an abstraction (which is [[#Physicality|itself an object]]).
:For example, ''[[#Simplification and ordering|picture 1 below]]'' illustrates the concrete relationship "Cat sits on Mat".
Chains of abstractions can be [[construe]]d,<ref name = Ross>Ross, L. (1987). The Problem of Construal in Social Inference and Social Psychology. In N. Grunberg, R.E. Nisbett, J. Singer (eds), ''A Distinctive Approach to psychological research: the influence of Stanley Schacter''. Hillsdale, NJ: Earlbaum.</ref> moving from neural impulses arising from sensory [[perception]] to basic abstractions such as color or [[shape]], to experiential abstractions such as a specific cat, to [[semantic]] abstractions such as the "idea" of a CAT, to classes of objects such as "mammals" and even categories such as "[[#Physicality|object]]" as opposed to "action".
:For example, ''[[#Simplification and ordering|graph 1 below]]'' expresses the abstraction "agent sits on location". This conceptual scheme entails no specific [[hierarchical]] [[Taxonomy (biology)|taxonomy]] (such as the one mentioned involving cats and mammals), only a progressive [[#Simplification and ordering|exclusion of detail]].

===Instantiation===

Non-existent things in any particular place and time are often seen as abstract. By contrast, instances, or members, of such an abstract thing might exist in many different places and times.

Those abstract things are then said to be ''multiply instantiated'', in the sense of ''picture 1'', ''picture 2'', etc., shown [[#Simplification and ordering|below]]. It is not sufficient, however, to define ''abstract'' ideas as those that can be instantiated and to define ''abstraction'' as the movement in the opposite direction to instantiation. Doing so would make the concepts "cat" and "telephone" abstract ideas since despite their varying appearances, a particular cat or a particular telephone is an instance of the concept "cat" or the concept "telephone". Although the concepts "cat" and "telephone" are ''abstractions'', they are not ''abstract'' in the sense of the objects in ''graph 1'' [[#Simplification and ordering|below]]. We might look at other graphs, in a progression from ''cat'' to ''mammal'' to ''animal'', and see that ''animal'' is more abstract than ''mammal''; but on the other hand ''mammal'' is a harder idea to express, certainly in relation to ''[[marsupial]]'' or ''[[monotreme]]''.

===Material process===
Still retaining the primary meaning of 'abstrere' or 'to draw away from', the abstraction of money, for example, works by drawing away from the particular value of things allowing completely incommensurate objects to be compared (see the section on 'Physicality' below). [[Karl Marx]]'s writing on the [[commodity]] abstraction recognizes a parallel process.

The [[state (polity)]] as both concept and material practice exemplifies the two sides of this process of abstraction. Conceptually, 'the current concept of the state is an abstraction from the much more concrete early-modern use as the standing or status of the prince, his visible estates'. At the same time, materially, the 'practice of statehood is now constitutively and materially more abstract than at the time when princes ruled as the embodiment of extended power'.<ref>{{Cite book | last= James | first= Paul |author-link= Paul James (academic) | title= Globalism, Nationalism, Tribalism: Bringing Theory Back In – Volume 2 of Towards a Theory of Abstract Community |url= https://www.academia.edu/1642214 | year= 2006 | publisher= Sage Publications | location= London }}, pp. 318–19.</ref> {{further|Power projection|Display behavior}}

===Ontological status===
The way that physical objects, like rocks and trees, have [[category of being|being]] differs from the way that properties of abstract concepts or relations have being, for example the way the [[concrete (philosophy)|concrete]], [[particular]], [[individual]]s pictured in ''[[#Simplification and ordering|picture 1]]'' exist differs from the way the concepts illustrated in ''[[#Simplification and ordering|graph 1]]'' exist. That difference accounts for the [[ontological]] usefulness of the word "abstract". The word applies to properties and relations to mark the fact that, if they exist, they do not exist in space or time, but that instances of them can exist, potentially in many different places and times.

===Physicality===
{{Further|History of accounting#Ancient history}}
A physical object (a possible referent of a concept or word) is considered ''concrete'' (not abstract) if it is a ''particular individual'' that occupies a particular place and time. However, in the secondary sense of the term 'abstraction', this physical object can carry materially abstracting processes. For example, record-keeping aids throughout the [[Fertile Crescent]] included calculi (clay spheres, cones, etc.) which represented counts of items, probably livestock or grains, sealed in containers. According to {{harvnb|Schmandt-Besserat|1981}}, these clay containers contained tokens, the total of which were the count of objects being transferred. The containers thus served as something of a [[bill of lading]] or an accounts book. In order to avoid breaking open the containers for the count, marks were placed on the outside of the containers. These physical marks, in other words, acted as material abstractions of a materially abstract process of accounting, using conceptual abstractions (numbers) to communicate its meaning.<ref>Eventually ([http://www.laits.utexas.edu/ghazal/Chap1/dsb/chapter1.html Schmandt-Besserat estimates it took 4000 years] {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120130084757/http://www.laits.utexas.edu/ghazal/Chap1/dsb/chapter1.html |date=January 30, 2012 }}) the marks on the outside of the containers were all that were needed to convey the count. The clay containers evolved into clay tablets with marks for the count.
</ref><ref>{{cite book|first=Eleanor|last=Robson|author-link=Eleanor Robson|year=2008|title=Mathematics in Ancient Iraq|isbn=978-0-691-09182-2}}. p. 5: these calculi were in use in Iraq for primitive accounting systems as early as 3200–3000 BCE, with commodity-specific counting representation systems. Balanced accounting was in use by 3000–2350 BCE, and a [[sexagesimal number system]] was in use 2350–2000 BCE.</ref>


== У математици ==
== У математици ==
Ред 43: Ред 73:


== Извори ==
== Извори ==
{{reflist}}
{{reflist|}}

== Литература ==
{{Refbegin|30em}}
* {{Cite book | last= James | first= Paul |author-link= Paul James (academic) | title= Nation Formation: Towards a Theory of Abstract Community | url= https://archive.org/details/nationformationt00jame
| url-access= registration |publisher= Sage Publications | location= London |year= 1996}}
* {{Cite book | last= James | first= Paul |author-link= Paul James (academic) | title= Globalism, Nationalism, Tribalism: Bringing Theory Back In - Volume 2 of Towards a Theory of Abstract Community |url= https://www.academia.edu/1642214 | year= 2006 | publisher= Sage Publications | location= London }}
* {{cite book| last = Jung | first = C.G. | edition = 1921 | year = 1971 | title = Psychological Types | series=Collected Works | volume = 6 | location = Princeton, NJ | publisher = Princeton University Press | isbn = 0-691-01813-8}}.
* {{cite book|title=The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 3rd edition | year = 1992 | publisher = Houghton Mifflin (1992) | isbn = 0-395-44895-6}}
* Sohn-Rethel, Alfred (1977) ''Intellectual and manual labour: A critique of epistemology'', Humanities Press.
* {{cite journal|last=Schmandt-Besserat|first=Denise|author-link=Denise Schmandt-Besserat|title=Decipherment of the Earliest Tablets|journal=Science|volume=211|pages=283–285|year=1981|doi=10.1126/science.211.4479.283|pmid=17748027|issue=4479
|bibcode=1981Sci...211..283S}}.
* {{cite book |url= https://www.researchgate.net/publication/263296077 |title= Early Human Behaviour in Global Context |first= Ravi |last= Korisettar | publisher= Routledge |year= 1998}}
* {{cite journal |last1= McBrearty |first1= Sally |last2= Brooks |first2= Allison |date= 2000 |title= The revolution that wasn't: a new interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior |journal= Journal of Human Evolution |volume= 39 |issue= 5 |pages= 453–563 |doi= 10.1006/jhev.2000.0435 |pmid= 11102266 | quote = Proponents of the model known as the 'human revolution' claim that modern human behaviors arose suddenly, and nearly simultaneously, throughout the Old World ca. 40–50 ka. [...] In fact, many of the components of the 'human revolution' claimed to appear at 40–50 ka are found in the African Middle Stone Age tens of thousands of years earlier. These features include blade and microlithic technology, bone tools, increased geographic range, specialized hunting, the use of aquatic resources, long distance trade, systematic processing and use of pigment, and art and decoration. }}
* {{cite journal |last1= Henshilwood |first1= Christopher |last2= Marean |first2= Curtis |date= 2003 |title= The Origin of Modern Human Behavior: Critique of the Models and Their Test Implications |journal= Current Anthropology |volume= 44 |issue= 5 |pages= 627–651 |doi= 10.1086/377665 |pmid= 14971366|s2cid= 11081605 }}
* {{cite journal |last1= Hill |first1= Kim |title= The Emergence of Human Uniqueness: Characters Underlying Behavioral Modernity |journal= Evolutionary Anthropology |date= 2009 |volume= 18 |issue= 5 |pages= 187–200 |display-authors= etal |doi= 10.1002/evan.20224 |citeseerx= 10.1.1.469.5702|s2cid= 56384790 }}
* {{cite journal |last1= D'Errico |first1= F |title= Neanderthal Acculturation in Western Europe? A Critical Review of the Evidence and Its Interpretation |journal= Current Anthropology |date= 1998 |volume= 39 |issue= S1 |page= S1–S44 |display-authors= etal |doi= 10.1086/204689|s2cid= 144799519 }}
* {{cite journal |last= Klein |first= Richard |title= Anatomy, behavior, and modern human origins |journal= Journal of World Prehistory |date= 1995 |volume= 9 |issue= 2 |pages= 167–198 |doi= 10.1007/bf02221838|s2cid= 10402296 }}
* {{cite journal |last1= McBrearty |first1= Sally |last2= Brooks |first2= Allison |date= 2000 |title= The revolution that wasn't: a new interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior |journal= Journal of Human Evolution |volume= 39 |issue= 5 |pages= 453–563 |doi= 10.1006/jhev.2000.0435 |pmid= 11102266 }}
* {{cite journal |last1= Marean |first1= Curtis |title= Early human use of marine resources and pigment in South Africa during the Middle Pleistocene |journal= Nature |date= 2007 |volume= 449 |issue= 7164 |display-authors= etal |doi= 10.1038/nature06204 |pages= 905–908 |pmid= 17943129 |bibcode= 2007Natur.449..905M|s2cid= 4387442 }}
* {{cite journal |last1= Powell |first1= Adam |title= Late Pleistocene Demography and the Appearance of Modern Human Behavior |journal= Science |date= 2009 |volume= 324 |issue= 5932 |pages= 1298–1301 |display-authors= etal |doi= 10.1126/science.1170165 |bibcode= 2009Sci...324.1298P |pmid= 19498164 |s2cid= 206518315 | url= http://doc.rero.ch/record/210393/files/PAL_E4401.pdf}}
* {{cite journal |last1= Premo |first1= Luke |last2= Kuhn |first2= Steve |title= Modeling Effects of Local Extinctions on Culture Change and Diversity in the Paleolithic |journal= PLOS ONE |date= 2010 |volume= 5 |issue= 12 |doi= 10.1371/journal.pone.0015582 |pages= e15582 |pmid= 21179418 |pmc= 3003693 |bibcode= 2010PLoSO...515582P
|doi-access= free }}
{{refend}}


== Спољашње везе==
== Спољашње везе==
{{Commonscat|Abstraction}}
{{Commonscat|Abstraction}}
* [http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/f/frege.htm Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Gottlob Frege]
* [http://originresearch.com/sd/sd1.cfm Discussion at The Well concerning Abstraction hierarchy]


{{нормативна контрола}}
{{нормативна контрола}}

Верзија на датум 3. јун 2022. у 19:49

Апстракција (лат. abstractio) је мисаоно издвајање неких особина и својстава предмета од самог предмета, као и апстрактан појам издвојен од нечега конкретног за који је везан. Апстрахирати или апстраховати (нем. abstrahieren): вршити апстракцију, и не узети (узимати) нешто у обзир, не обазрети се, не обазирати се на нешто. Апстрактно: добијено апстракцијом, мисаоно; супротно од конкретно. Фактички, када је нешто апстрактно, то значи да се нешто не односи само на једну појединост, већ на неку већу целину, скуп нечега и сл. Апстрактно мишљење је врста мишљења која се одликује тиме да високо надилази перцептивни ниво и конкретне појаве и да оперише апстрактним симболима.[1]

Порекло

Thinking in abstractions is considered by anthropologists, archaeologists, and sociologists to be one of the key traits in modern human behaviour, which is believed to have developed between 50,000 and 100,000 years ago. Its development is likely to have been closely connected with the development of human language, which (whether spoken or written) appears to both involve and facilitate abstract thinking.

Историја

Abstraction involves induction of ideas or the synthesis of particular facts into one general theory about something. It is the opposite of specification, which is the analysis or breaking-down of a general idea or abstraction into concrete facts. Abstraction can be illustrated by Francis Bacon's Novum Organum (1620), a book of modern scientific philosophy written in the late Jacobean era[2] of England to encourage modern thinkers to collect specific facts before making any generalizations.

Bacon used and promoted induction as an abstraction tool; it complemented but was distinct from the ancient deductive-thinking approach that had dominated the intellectual world since the times of Greek philosophers like Thales, Anaximander, and Aristotle.[3] Thales (c. 624–546 BCE) believed that everything in the universe comes from one main substance, water. He deduced or specified from a general idea, "everything is water," to the specific forms of water such as ice, snow, fog, and rivers.

Modern scientists can also use the opposite approach of abstraction, or going from particular facts collected into one general idea, such as the motion of the planets (Newton (1642–1727)). When determining that the sun is the center of our solar system (Copernicus (1473–1543)), scientists had to use thousands of measurements to finally conclude that Mars moves in an elliptical orbit about the sun (Kepler (1571–1630)), or to assemble multiple specific facts into the law of falling bodies (Galileo (1564–1642)).

Теме

Compression

An abstraction can be seen as a compression process,[4] mapping multiple different pieces of constituent data to a single piece of abstract data;[5] based on similarities in the constituent data, for example, many different physical cats map to the abstraction "CAT". This conceptual scheme emphasizes the inherent equality of both constituent and abstract data, thus avoiding problems arising from the distinction between "abstract" and "concrete". In this sense the process of abstraction entails the identification of similarities between objects, and the process of associating these objects with an abstraction (which is itself an object).

For example, picture 1 below illustrates the concrete relationship "Cat sits on Mat".

Chains of abstractions can be construed,[6] moving from neural impulses arising from sensory perception to basic abstractions such as color or shape, to experiential abstractions such as a specific cat, to semantic abstractions such as the "idea" of a CAT, to classes of objects such as "mammals" and even categories such as "object" as opposed to "action".

For example, graph 1 below expresses the abstraction "agent sits on location". This conceptual scheme entails no specific hierarchical taxonomy (such as the one mentioned involving cats and mammals), only a progressive exclusion of detail.

Instantiation

Non-existent things in any particular place and time are often seen as abstract. By contrast, instances, or members, of such an abstract thing might exist in many different places and times.

Those abstract things are then said to be multiply instantiated, in the sense of picture 1, picture 2, etc., shown below. It is not sufficient, however, to define abstract ideas as those that can be instantiated and to define abstraction as the movement in the opposite direction to instantiation. Doing so would make the concepts "cat" and "telephone" abstract ideas since despite their varying appearances, a particular cat or a particular telephone is an instance of the concept "cat" or the concept "telephone". Although the concepts "cat" and "telephone" are abstractions, they are not abstract in the sense of the objects in graph 1 below. We might look at other graphs, in a progression from cat to mammal to animal, and see that animal is more abstract than mammal; but on the other hand mammal is a harder idea to express, certainly in relation to marsupial or monotreme.

Material process

Still retaining the primary meaning of 'abstrere' or 'to draw away from', the abstraction of money, for example, works by drawing away from the particular value of things allowing completely incommensurate objects to be compared (see the section on 'Physicality' below). Karl Marx's writing on the commodity abstraction recognizes a parallel process.

The state (polity) as both concept and material practice exemplifies the two sides of this process of abstraction. Conceptually, 'the current concept of the state is an abstraction from the much more concrete early-modern use as the standing or status of the prince, his visible estates'. At the same time, materially, the 'practice of statehood is now constitutively and materially more abstract than at the time when princes ruled as the embodiment of extended power'.[7]

Ontological status

The way that physical objects, like rocks and trees, have being differs from the way that properties of abstract concepts or relations have being, for example the way the concrete, particular, individuals pictured in picture 1 exist differs from the way the concepts illustrated in graph 1 exist. That difference accounts for the ontological usefulness of the word "abstract". The word applies to properties and relations to mark the fact that, if they exist, they do not exist in space or time, but that instances of them can exist, potentially in many different places and times.

Physicality

A physical object (a possible referent of a concept or word) is considered concrete (not abstract) if it is a particular individual that occupies a particular place and time. However, in the secondary sense of the term 'abstraction', this physical object can carry materially abstracting processes. For example, record-keeping aids throughout the Fertile Crescent included calculi (clay spheres, cones, etc.) which represented counts of items, probably livestock or grains, sealed in containers. According to Schmandt-Besserat 1981, these clay containers contained tokens, the total of which were the count of objects being transferred. The containers thus served as something of a bill of lading or an accounts book. In order to avoid breaking open the containers for the count, marks were placed on the outside of the containers. These physical marks, in other words, acted as material abstractions of a materially abstract process of accounting, using conceptual abstractions (numbers) to communicate its meaning.[8][9]

У математици

Апстракција, односно апстраховање у математици је процес разматрања извесних особина објеката изостављањем других које нису релевантне. То је основа класификовања, процедуре која резултује скупом чланова са посебним особинама. Поменути скуп се означава са чит. икс такво да је еф од икс, односно х које има особину F(х), где је F(х) својство које чланови скупа морају задовољити. На пример, {x:x је птица}, означава скуп у којем су сви елементи птице.

Аксиома апстракције

Нека је дата произвољна особина f(x), тада постоји скуп чији чланови поседују баш ту особину, тј.

Наведена аксиома апстракције је први пут експлицитно формулисана од стране Фригеа 1893. године, да би затим, од стране Расела, била доведена у контрадикцију:

Нека је дата особина F(x), поменутог аксиома, особина не-припадања самом себи. Тада је

аксиом избора, који једноставним корацима води у контрадикцију

Да би избегао овај, тзв. Раселов парадокс, Зермело је 1908. увео аксиом сепарације:

у којем егзистенција скупа у није више претпостављена безусловно.

Види још

Извори

  1. ^ Овај део чланка је преузет из књиге Ивана Видановића „Речник социјалног рада“ уз одобрење аутора.
  2. ^ Hesse, M. B. (1964), "Francis Bacon's Philosophy of Science", in A Critical History of Western Philosophy, ed. D. J. O'Connor, New York, pp. 141–52.
  3. ^ Klein, Jürgen (2016), „Francis Bacon”, Ур.: Zalta, Edward N., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 изд.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Приступљено 2019-10-22 
  4. ^ Chaitin, Gregory (2006), „The Limits Of Reason” (PDF), Scientific American, 294 (3): 74—81, Bibcode:2006SciAm.294c..74C, PMID 16502614, doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0306-74, Архивирано из оригинала (PDF) 2015-05-09. г. 
  5. ^ Murray Gell-Mann (1995) "What is complexity? Remarks on simplicity and complexity by the Nobel Prize-winning author of The Quark and the Jaguar" Complexity states the 'algorithmic information complexity' (AIC) of some string of bits is the shortest length computer program which can print out that string of bits.
  6. ^ Ross, L. (1987). The Problem of Construal in Social Inference and Social Psychology. In N. Grunberg, R.E. Nisbett, J. Singer (eds), A Distinctive Approach to psychological research: the influence of Stanley Schacter. Hillsdale, NJ: Earlbaum.
  7. ^ James, Paul (2006). Globalism, Nationalism, Tribalism: Bringing Theory Back In – Volume 2 of Towards a Theory of Abstract Community. London: Sage Publications. , pp. 318–19.
  8. ^ Eventually (Schmandt-Besserat estimates it took 4000 years Архивирано јануар 30, 2012 на сајту Wayback Machine) the marks on the outside of the containers were all that were needed to convey the count. The clay containers evolved into clay tablets with marks for the count.
  9. ^ Robson, Eleanor (2008). Mathematics in Ancient Iraq. ISBN 978-0-691-09182-2. . p. 5: these calculi were in use in Iraq for primitive accounting systems as early as 3200–3000 BCE, with commodity-specific counting representation systems. Balanced accounting was in use by 3000–2350 BCE, and a sexagesimal number system was in use 2350–2000 BCE.

Литература

Спољашње везе